npm package discovery and stats viewer.

Discover Tips

  • General search

    [free text search, go nuts!]

  • Package details

    pkg:[package-name]

  • User packages

    @[username]

Sponsor

Optimize Toolset

I’ve always been into building performant and accessible sites, but lately I’ve been taking it extremely seriously. So much so that I’ve been building a tool to help me optimize and monitor the sites that I build to make sure that I’m making an attempt to offer the best experience to those who visit them. If you’re into performant, accessible and SEO friendly sites, you might like it too! You can check it out at Optimize Toolset.

About

Hi, 👋, I’m Ryan Hefner  and I built this site for me, and you! The goal of this site was to provide an easy way for me to check the stats on my npm packages, both for prioritizing issues and updates, and to give me a little kick in the pants to keep up on stuff.

As I was building it, I realized that I was actually using the tool to build the tool, and figured I might as well put this out there and hopefully others will find it to be a fast and useful way to search and browse npm packages as I have.

If you’re interested in other things I’m working on, follow me on Twitter or check out the open source projects I’ve been publishing on GitHub.

I am also working on a Twitter bot for this site to tweet the most popular, newest, random packages from npm. Please follow that account now and it will start sending out packages soon–ish.

Open Software & Tools

This site wouldn’t be possible without the immense generosity and tireless efforts from the people who make contributions to the world and share their work via open source initiatives. Thank you 🙏

© 2024 – Pkg Stats / Ryan Hefner

escoc

v0.1.2

Published

A nano proof language.

Downloads

9

Readme

ESCoC: Expanded-Scope Calculus of Constructions

A nano (500 JS LOC, including parser and bidirectional type-checker) "theorem prover" capable of inductive reasoning. Compared to Cedille-Core, ESCoC is 1. much simpler to implement, 2. much simpler to use, due to lack of redundancy. But it has no consistency proof (see the point at the end).

Usage

npm i -g escoc
escoc main.escoc

ESCoC was initially implemented in JS for no special reason, but a Haskell/Rust version would be nice and smaller.

Why?

I believe elegance is an important heuristics of mathematical exploration. Whenever a mathematical problem is solved in a complex, "human-engineered" manner, such solution is probably broken, and a correct, elegant, simple and clever solution probably exists, waiting to be found. Designing a proof language may be one of those things waiting for an elegant solution. Proof assistants such as Coq and Agda are built by extending an arguably elegant language (CoC) with inductive datatypes, a complex system that feels suspiciously human-engineered. This is necessary to enable inductive reasoning, essential to mathematical practice, and which CoC unfortunately lacks. Under this point of view, exploring simpler alternatives to inductive datatypes is valuable, because it might let us find such "elegant solution".

How it works?

ESCoC takes the CoC and 1. expands the scope of the dependent function type, so that, in Π (x : A) B, x is bound in A, 2. enables recursive definitions. And that's it. Notice that there are no extra primitives such as dependent intersections or self types, and no fundamental changes such as involving untyped terms in equality checking. ESCoC doesn't extend (recursive) CoC with anything new, just expands in a very minor way its existing constructs. To explain it, remember that, in CoC, the return type of a function can depend on its argument. That is, in an application such as (f a), if the type of f is Π (x : A) B, then the type of (f a) is [a/x]B. The difference is that, in ESCoC, the input type of a function can also depend on its argument. That is, in an application such as (f a), instead of checking if a : A, we check if a : [a/x]A. ESCoC is defined by the following syntax:

term ::=
  Type              -- the type of types
  {var : term} term -- dependent function type
  [var : term] term -- a lambda
  (term term)       -- an application
  var : term = term -- a recursive definition
  var               -- a variable

And the following typing rules:


----------- type in type (temporary?)
Type : Type

(var, type) in ctx
------------------ variables
ctx |- var : type

ctx, x : A |- A : Type    ctx, x : A |- B : Type
------------------------------------------------ pi (dependent function type)
ctx |- {x : A} B : Type

ctx, x : A |- f : B    ctx |- {a : A} B : Type
---------------------------------------------- lambda (dependent function intro)
ctx |- [x : A] B : {x : A} B

ctx |- f : {x : A} B    ctx |- a : [a/x]A
----------------------------------------- application (dependent function elim)
ctx |- (f a) : [a/x]B

Notice that the only change with respect to (recursive) CoC is that x is always bound in A. This is simple to implement, and any CoC implementation can adopt it with almost no change.

How can one implement inductive datatypes on it?

To start with a simple example, let's see the Boolean type. In Agda, you'd write it as such:

data Bool : Set where
  true  : Bool
  false : Bool

That is, it is just a type without constructors. Inductive proofs can be expressed with:

elim : (b : Bool) -> (P : Bool -> Set) -> P true -> P false -> P b
elim true  P t f = t
elim false P t f = f

In CoC, you can represent booleans with Church-encodings:

Bool : Type =
  {Prop  : Type}
  {true  : Prop}
  {false : Prop}
  Prop

true  : Bool = [Prop] [true] [false] true
false : Bool = [Prop] [true] [false] false

(Note that I'll hide the type annotations of lambdas when they can be recovered by bidirectional type checking.) This isn't too different from the Agda definition, other than the need to write Prop instead of Bool. This is because the Church-encoding represents a datatype as its own fold, and Prop allows us to define type returned when folding over it. Unfortunatelly, there is no way to implement elimination for such a type. In ESCoC, you're able to represent indutive booleans as their own induction principles:

Bool
: {self  : (Bool self)} Type
= [self]
  {Prop  : {self : (Bool self)} Type}
  {true  : (Prop Bool.true)}
  {false : (Prop Bool.false)}
  (Prop self)

Bool.true  : (Bool Bool.true)  = [Prop] [true] [false] true
Bool.false : (Bool Bool.false) = [Prop] [true] [false] false

Compared to the former representation, the main change is that, now, Bool isn't a type, but a function that receives a Bool and returns a type. It also refers to its own constructors, Bool.true and Bool.false, in a mutually recursive fashion; this is the reason we don't need dependent intersections. There isn't a single Bool type, but many: Bool.true, for example, isn't of type Bool, but of type (Bool BOol.true), which is different of the type of false, which is (Bool Bool.false). But that's not a problem in practice, because we're still able to implement functions that operate on both:

id
: {b : (Bool b)} (Bool b)
= [b] self

This is the main power of ESCoC: it can express "super-polymorphic" functions that operate on different types, as long as they are "indexed by their own values". So, despite true and false having different types, they can still be used as one. This allows us to implement induction easily:

Bool.induct
: {self  : (Bool self)}
  {Prop  : {self : (Bool self)} Type}
  {true  : (Prop Bool.true)}
  {false : (Prop Bool.false)}
  (Prop self)
= [self] [Prop] [true] [false]
  (self Prop true false)

This is just identity because, under this encoding, datatypes are represented precisely by their induction principles. Now you might be wondering: how do we implement something like not? If we try this:

Bool.not
: {b : (Bool b)} (Bool b)
= [b] (b
  [b](Bool b)
  Bool.false
  Bool.true)

We get a type error. The problem is that, when setting the return type, we wrote (Bool b), where b is the value of the input, yet, on the Bool.true case, we returned Bool.false, which has type (Bool Bool.false), not (Bool Bool.true). We could fix this issue by flipping the arguments, but then that'd turn it into the identity function, not the negation. What we want is to change the return type:

Bool.not
: {b : (Bool b)} (Bool (Bool.not b))
= [b] (b
  [b](Bool (Bool.not b))
  Bool.false
  Bool.true)

This now says that not is a function that takes a Bool indexed on itself, and returns a Bool indexed on its negation. So, for example, if you give it true : (Bool true), then it will return a false : (Bool (not true)). Recursive types like Nat can be done using the same concept:

Nat
: {self : (Nat self)} Type
= [self]
  {Prop  : {self : (Nat self)} Type}
  {succ  : {pred : (Nat pred)} (Prop (Nat.succ pred))}
  {zero  : (Prop Nat.zero)}
  (Prop self)

Nat.succ
: {pred : (Nat pred)} (Nat (Nat.succ pred))
= [pred] [Nat.] [succ.] [zero.]
  (succ. pred)

Nat.zero
: (Nat Nat.zero)
= [Nat.] [succ.] [zero.] zero.

Here, again, Nat is a type indexed on itself. The only difference is that the succ case has an extra field, pred, which is, as expected, (Nat pred). This realizes the Scott-encoding, which are computationally equivalent to Haskell's algebraic datatypes. One can implement inductive Parigot and Church encodings too, but I'm not sure if it is possible to implement certain recursive functions such as is_even : {n : (PNat n)} (Bool (is_even n)). Equality can be implemented as such:

Eq
: {T    : {self : (T self)} Type}
  {a    : (T a)}
  {b    : (T b)}
  {self : (Eq T a b self)}
  Type
= [T] [a] [b] [self]
  {Prop : {b : (T b)} {self : (Eq T a b self)} Type}
  {refl : (Prop a (Eq.refl T a))}
  (Prop b self)

Eq.refl
: {T : {self : (T self)} Type}
  {a : (T a)}
  (Eq T a a (Eq.refl T a))
= [T] [a] [Prop] [refl]
  refl

Notice that this is basically the J axiom, with one difference: instead of being parameterized T : Type, it is parameterized by a T : {self : (T self)} Type, allowing you to express equalities on self-referential types. Something interesting about this representation is that, since Eq is indexed on itself, its type essentially carries the evidence of equality around. I'm not sure what this implies. More examples can be seen on the main.escoc file, including some simple theorems on those types.

But what about consistency?

CoC with equirecursion isn't consistent, as it is trivial to inhabit the empty type:

loop : {P : Type} P = loop

But it shouldn't be hard to use ESCoC as the foundation of a consistent language. If we, for example, simply restrict recursion to positive type ocurrences, then, I believe we could easily prove strong normalization by erasure to Fω, as done on the Self Types paper. This would allow us to, for example, use Parigot (but not Scott) encodings for inductive reasoning. An alternative would be to use alternatives to classic logic, such as light logics, which, as argued on the paper, are consistent even in the presence of arbitrary type recursion. This may be attractive for a bunch of reasons, as it simplifies the theory and allows efficient compilation to interaction combinators. This repository will not include any particular restriction though, as it should be just a template to explore those ideas. Termination is to be considered a separate concern that must be addressed when using ESCoC as the foundation of another language.